Clausewitz served in the Russian army during the Napoleonic war of 1812 and his influence in Russia is felt to this day. Indeed, Russia’s approach to the war in Ukraine has the imprint of Clausewitz in the sense that it sees military action as a political instrument, along with other such instruments, such as diplomatic and economic ones.
This helps to explain why Russia has been somewhat misunderstood in Western political and intellectual circles as the current crisis has escalated. Since the end of the Cold War, Western elites have come to equate war with the particular military doctrine of the United States, for which, contrary to Clausewitz, war only starts where politics ends, or even worse: when war of aggression is the preferred means to reach political and commercial ends, often at the exclusion of any good faith diplomacy (the 1998 so-called “negotiations” at Rambouillet come to mind).
Washington’s wars in the Middle East are typical examples of this. The consequences of these wars have of course been disastrous for the victim states, but they have also been negative for the United States, for instance in terms of increased militarism and exploding debt. The official objectives of these wars, such as “spreading democracy”, have never really been achieved. Instead, the Military-Industrial Complex has profited massively from these wars, which strongly suggests that the real military goals of the US government are not the official ones.
For Clausewitz, writing in a time when crony capitalism hardly existed, there is a fundamental interest in avoiding war, because war harms all parties directly involved. Thus, in this light, war should always be the last resort employed by States when trying to reach political goals, not only because of the loss of life and the destruction of property that war entails, but also because of the uncertainty of war for all involved. As the old saying goes, it is easy to start a war, but difficult to end it.
When war does erupt, it is thus often the result of one side’s error of judgment with regard to its own and its opponent’s capabilities and intentions. As the historian Carroll Quigley wrote in his magnum opus, Tragedy and Hope: “This is the chief function of war: to demonstrate as conclusively as possible to mistaken minds that they are mistaken in regard to power relationships.”
If the losing party of a war had properly understood its outcome beforehand, if it were rational it would have done what was necessary to avoid it, even if that meant painful concessions to a stronger rival. Many historical examples come to mind which fit this description, e.g. Germany’s misjudgement in WWI and Japan’s in WWII. Today, the West’s underestimation of Russia’s economic and military capabilities, and the Ukrainian government’s stubbornness in pursuing a losing campaign at great cost, are also glaring examples of Quigley’s insight.
Since the decision to go to war has serious and unpredictable consequences, it should not be taken lightly, but reluctantly. Thus, the wisdom in George Santayana’s words: “To delight in war is a merit in the soldier, a dangerous quality in the captain, and a positive crime in the statesman.” Unfortunately, several recent Western leaders, from US President Bush in Afghanistan, to UK Prime Minister Blair in Iraq, and French President Sarkozy in Libya, have confirmed this remark by their reckless disregard for the consequences of military action.
The Lack of Relevance of the U.N.
Typically for a 19th century thinker, Clausewitz accepts the possibility for war to solve political problems, in a way modern international law does not. However, his view of war seems more respectful of the U.N. Charter than the aggressive military doctrine practiced by some of its Western signatories. Indeed, the United Nation’s Security Council’s past decisions to allow military intervention have often not met even the Clausewitz rationale for war; namely the exhaustion of all other means of issue resolution.
U.N. Security Council authorisations that since 1945 have allowed some member States to use force against other members, have often had underlying interests other than the stated one of “restoring international peace”. Predictably, the results of many of these U.N. sanctioned military interventions have generally been disastrous; often exacerbating conflicts and leading to the dramatic suffering of the civilian populations. Truly shocking examples are the following US military interventions that made a mockery of the U.N.’s ideal of peace:
- · North Korea 1950; the infamous US “police action” approved under UN Charter
Article 42, during the absence of the USSR’s representative to the U.N.
Security Council,
- · South Vietnam 1966; Article 51, South Vietnam’s self-defence used as a pretext
to allow US escalation in the war in Vietnam, leading to millions of casualties
- · Kuwait 1990; Article 42, which started three decades of US onslaught on Iraq,
- · Libya 2011; Chapter VII, invoked while Russia and China made the error of
abstaining, and finally the scope of which was not respected by NATO.
The U.N.
has had a problem of legitimacy and objectivity since its inception, which has
been aggravated since the end of the Cold War. It has indeed been accused, often
with good reason, of being a tool of US foreign policy, as the previously
mentioned resolutions highlight.
Even
worse, the UN Charter and the legal legitimacy of the U.N. Security Council (UNSC)
have simply been disregarded by the US government in Serbia in 1999 and Iraq in
2003, setting a dangerous precedent. Today, of the permanent five veto-wielding
members of the UNSC, three of them are now adversaries of the other two, and
this is preventing the UNSC from making any significant contribution towards restoring
peace.
What
kept the peace, at least in Europe, between the two geostrategic and
ideological Cold War rivals was arguably more the nuclear deterrence than the
existence of the U.N. Charter, even though the USA and the USSR did several
times come close to using nuclear weapons.
The UN’s role in enforcing international law
is therefore today almost non-existent. The absence of the UN in helping solve
the current conflict between Russia and NATO is glaring. The UN Charter is thus
simply a legal framework that works - de
facto, not de jure - only as long
as all of its most powerful members adhere to it in both spirit and letter. In
reality, international relations between Nation-States are still to a large extent
power relationship, as in the days of Clausewitz.
Realism Complemented by Libertarianism
The view of modern war presented above, however realist in its outlook, does not consider the cause of war in the first place. It seems inevitable that this requires a focus on the role of the modern State as the instigator of all wars. Therefore, however insightful Clausewitz’s commentary on war, it should be complemented by a theory of the modern State.
Libertarianism is perfectly placed for this task since it identifies the State as the cause of most of society’s artificially created ills. As a political philosophy based on natural right, libertarianism cannot morally accept a war waged by the State, even if an entirely defensive one (if there is such a thing). The State, by its very definition, violates the non-aggression principle by its monopoly of violence on a given territory.
In practice, however, even a libertarian would have to prefer the case of a State’s non-interested protection of private property in a defensive war against an external enemy, to the alternative of an externally imposed tyranny. Yet, the real world rarely reoffers such clear choices.
Free trade, i.e. is trade completely unobstructed by national or supranational States, is the main driver for peace between nations. Open, trading nations have an interest in peaceful relations with other each other and are therefore naturally averse to war. Protectionism and the tendency towards autarky are both causes and consequences of fraught relations between States that can lead to military conflict. This is not surprising since the stakes of the State in society, through its intervention in the economy, introduces a logic of competition against other Nation-States.
Indeed, peace and prosperity in any society is inversely correlated to the size and strength of the State. In a world composed of Nations-States, this leads to the conclusion that is in complete opposition to political globalism; namely, that there should be as many of States as possible – why not down to the municipal level - so as to render each one as weak and limited as possible.
The concepts of secession and self-determination is therefore key for libertarians in order for the number of States to multiply. War becomes less likely the smaller and the less powerful States are, and the more similar to each other they are in size. The current times have shown the danger of States becoming so large as to have geopolitical interests; in the case of the USA, spanning the entire world.
In conclusion, it should be clear that is no contradiction between having a realist view of the world and at the same time one based on political principles. Having a realist view of international relations, as those presented here, does not preclude also recognizing the importance of the libertarian principles regarding war and the State. Indeed, only when the people start massively rejecting the interventions of their State abroad as well as domestically will the possibility for peace between States appear.
No comments:
Post a Comment